Hermetica: The Greek Corpus Hermeticum and the Latin Asclepius in a New ... - Google Books
Thoth's lunar bird Ibis
Horus's solar daytime bird hawk
in the house of rests of Ibis (burial)
what happened just
from Memphis to Alexandrie
through Antinopolis?
***
quotation:
1
GRAHAM LIVESEY (UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY)
(http://whiteheadresearch.org/occasions/conferences/event-and-decision/#participants)
Deleuze, Whitehead, the Event, and the Contemporary City
The “event” has pervaded the work of many thinkers over the last several decades from
phenomenologists, structuralists, to post-structuralists; for many the event is the constituent
element of a narrative. In A Dictionary of Narratology we find that an event is defined as a
“change of state manifested in discourse by a process statement in the mode of do or happen. An
event can be an action or act or a happening. Along with existents [subjects and/or objects]
events are the fundamental constituents of a story.”1 This underscores the notion that events are
the essential components of any narrative. Narratives are structured by plots and, following the
phenomenologist Paul Ricoeur, make both time human, and give sense to human lives; according
to this theory an event exists because of its ability to contribute to a plot. Many argue that
narratives pervade cities at all levels, from the everyday lives of its citizens to the general history
of a city. There is also the belief that provocative urban narratives are an aspect lacking in many
public or open spaces in cities.
As presented above, the conventional definition of the event and its relationship to narrative has
had an influence on some architects and urbanists during the last half century. For example, the
prominent Italian architect Aldo Rossi used the notion of the event as a central idea is his
seminal texts The Architecture of the City and A Scientific Autobiography; Rossi has written that
architecture is “the fixed stage for human events.”2 Structuralism and post-structuralism
influenced a group of architects involved at the Architectural Association during the 1970s and
1 Gerald Prince, A Dictionary of Narratology (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1987), p. 28.
2
which included Bernard Tschumi, Nigel Coates, and Rem Koolhaas; Tschumi has written that
“there is no space without event, no architecture without programme.”3 The adoption of theories
of events by architects and urbanists provided one basis for examining how space can be used, or
how architectural and urban space could create events. Much of this was consistent with attacks
on modernist urbanism that have occurred since the 1960s, and the broadly shared opinion that
modernist urban space was void of meaning and vitality.
However, there are other definitions of the event that have pervaded aspects of twentieth century
thinking that provide a different, more elusive, and potentially more comprehensive way of
thinking about how events shape the world. For example, the event is one of the central
concepts in Gilles Deleuze’s work; this remains a relatively unstudied aspect, in the worlds of
architecture and urbanism, of his influential writings. Deleuze, the philosopher of “becoming,”
provides an important, and challenging, body of work that attempts to understand the
complexities of the contemporary world. In this essay we will explore the implications for
Deleuze’s notion of event, and its origins, on contemporary urbanism. Cliff Stagoll, in The
Deleuze Dictionary, explains that for Deleuze an event arises from a set of particular forces, and
stands alone as an indication of the immanent and chaotic nature of the world.4 In his definition
of Deleuze’s concept of “becoming” Stagoll writes “every event is but a unique instant of
production in a continual flow of changes evident in the cosmos. The only thing ‘shared’ by
2 Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the City (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1982), p. 22.
3 Bernard Tschumi, “Spaces and Events,” in The Discourse of Events (London: Architectural Association, 1983), p.
6.
4 Adrian Parr, ed., The Deleuze Dictionary (New York, Columbia University Press, 2005), pp. 87-88.
3
events is their having become different in the course of their production.”5 Therefore, there is no
particular linkage between events and narrative in Deleuze’s work.
Deleuze examines the theory of the event primarily in his books The Logic of Sense and The
Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, although the event can also be found as a concept elsewhere in
his writings. In the earlier text, The Logic of Sense, which is an extended study of sense and
nonsense through the theories of the Stoics, Lewis Carroll, and Péguy, Deleuze devotes several
sections to the event. In the ninth series he describes “singularity” and the idealistic aspect of
events. He writes:
Singularities are turning points and points of inflection; bottlenecks, knots, foyers, and
centers; points of fusion, condensation, and boiling; points of tears and joy, sickness and
health, hope and anxiety, “sensitive” points.6
In the twenty-fourth series Deleuze tackles the difficult question of what might link events
together, drawing on Leibniz and Nietzsche. Here he writes:
Between events, there seem to be formed extrinsic relations of silent compatibility and
incompatibility, or conjunction and disjunction, which are very difficult to apprehend.7
In the twenty-sixth series he affirms that events do belong to language.8
5 Ibid., p. 22.
6 Gilles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990), p. 52.
7 Ibid., p. 170.
8 Ibid., p. 181.
4
In a subsequent book, The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, Deleuze develops and modifies his
theory of the event. In a chapter entitled “What is an Event?,” Deleuze draws directly from
Alfred North Whitehead’s definition of the event, as he demonstrates a more precise definition of
the term. He describes four conditions of the event: 1) extension, 2) intensities, 3) the individual
and “prehensions,” and 4) eternal objects or “ingressions.”9 At this point, the definition of the
event that will be developed in the remainder of this essay will explore this definition that
Deleuze derives from Whitehead. In Whitehead’s work he devotes extensive study to the event
in his texts The Concept of Nature (published 1920) and Process and Reality (published 1929).
If we look at the four conditions for the event that Deleuze identifies, we begin with extension.
Events address time and space, particularly with respect to time as the passage of events, which
raises Whitehead’s assertion of the “extensive relation between events.”10 In The Concept of
Nature, in the chapter entitled “The Method of Extensive Abstraction,” Whitehead notes that the
relations between events are transitive, and that events are parts of other events.11 He writes: “In
respect to extension two events are mutually related so that either (i) one include the other, or
(ii) one overlaps without complete inclusion, or (iii) they are entirely separate.”12 For Deleuze,
the event forms part of an infinite series, with, as Whitehead states, events inter-related with one
another.13 Alain Badiou, in his essay “The Event in Deleuze,” develops four axioms of the event
based on his reading of Deleuze’s work. According to Badiou, Deleuze’s second axiom states
9 Gilles Deleuze, The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993), pp. 77-
80.
10 Alfred North Whitehead, The Concept of Nature (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 2004), p. 34.
11 Ibid., p. 76.
12 Ibid., pp. 185-86.
13 Deleuze, The Fold, p. 77.
5
that the event is a “synthesis of past and future,”14 or to quote Deleuze, the event “is always that
which has just happened and that which is about to happen, but never that which is happening.”15
Here the importance of time is underscored and that, for Deleuze, the present is not
determinable. The extensive aspects of the event address the spatial and temporal aspects of
events and the relationships between events; the world could be composed (musically,
architecturally, etc.) of patterns or infinite series of events. R.G. Collingwood emphasizes the
extensive aspect of Whitehead’s theories and stresses that there is an “aim,” or vital teleological
dimension, to Whitehead’s process of becoming.16
In the second part of Whitehead’s definition, Deleuze writes that events have “intrinsic
properties (for example, height, intensity, timbre of a sound, a tint, a value, a saturation of color),
which enter on their own account in new infinite series, now converging towards limits, with the
relation among limits establishing a conjunction.”17 In particular the intensity of a property is
part of an event. Deleuze’s third axiom, according to Badiou, notes that while the event
“intensifies bodies, concentrates their constitutive multiplicity” it is not of the same nature as the
bodies it affects.18
The third component embraces Whitehead’s notion of the individual, with an emphasis on
creativity or the production of new events. Here we encounter Whitehead’s theory of
“prehension,” which he develops in texts such as Process and Reality. According to Lewis S.
Ford this is Whitehead’s definition of what is more commonly known as “experience” or
14 Alain Badiou, “The Event in Deleuze,” Parrhesia (Number 2, 2007), p. 38.
15 Ibid., p. 38.
16 See R.G. Collingwood, The Idea of Nature (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1945), pp. 165-174.
17 Deleuze, The Fold, p. 77.
6
“feeling,” or Deleuze’s concept of “affect.” Lewis writes that prehension for Whitehead means,
“any (conscious or unconscious) “taking account” of another, such that the prehender is affected
by what is prehended.”19 A prehension is a relationship between entities.20 Deleuze writes:
…the event is inseparably the objectification of one prehension and the subjectification of
another; it is at once public and private, potential and real, participating in the becoming of
another event and the subject of its own becoming.21
In the fourth aspect of the definition Whitehead discusses objects as part of events. The
relationship is defined by what he calls “ingression.” Whitehead writes:
The ingression of an object into an event is the way the character of the event shapes itself in
virtue of the being of the object. Namely the event is what it is, because the object is what it
is; and when I am thinking of this modification of the event by the object, I call the relation
between the two ‘the ingression of the object into the event.’ It is equally true to say that
objects are what they are because events are what they are.22
Whitehead identifies three kinds of objects: 1) sense-objects, 2) perceptual objects, and 3)
scientific objects. The sense-object is the most fundamental and can include colours, sounds,
smells, or feelings. Perceptual objects include physical objects such as furniture or buildings.
18 Badiou, “The Event in Deleuze,” p. 38.
19 Lewis S. Ford, “Afterword,” in L.S. Ford and G.L. Kline, eds., Explorations in Whitehead’s Philosophy (New
York: Fordham University Press, 1983), p. 329.
20 William A. Christian Sr., “Some Aspects of Whitehead’s Metaphysics,” in Ford and Kline, eds., Explorations in
Whitehead’s Philosophy, p. 33.
21 Deleuze, The Fold, p. 78.
7
Whitehead dose not address scientific objects in detail, suggesting they lie outside his theory.
According to Whitehead, objects “convey the permanences recognized in events.” 23
In summary, Whitehead writes: “Events are lived through, they extend around us. They are the
medium within which our physical experience develops, or, rather, they are themselves the
development of that experience.”24 In a text on Whitehead, originally published in 1942,
Stephen Lee Ely also summarizes Whitehead’s notion of events, he writes:
The world is not a thing it is a process….We recognize, first of all, that the underlying drive
of things expresses itself in a diversified plurality, an ever-changing, ever-renewed complex
of events. Further, the underlying drive is an activity in which novelties incessantly and
necessarily emerge: for whatever has already happened makes a difference to each newly
born event….The world-process is one in which the component events so interpenetrate that
each influences every other, and it is these influences thus received and felt that constitute
the material out of which each nascent event is constructed.25
The theory of event expounded by Deleuze in The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, derived
mainly from Whitehead, is based in part on Whitehead’s critical interpretation of Einstein’s
Theory of Relativity. Leibniz, Whitehead, and Deleuze are philosophers of becoming,
addressing the complexity and chaos of the world; they are also philosophers of the event. They
22 Whitehead, The Concept of Nature, p. 144.
23 Alfred North Whitehead, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge (Cambridge: University
Press, 1955), p. 62.
24 Ibid., p. 63.
25 Stephen Lee Ely, “The Religious Availability of Whitehead’s God: A Critical Analysis,” in Ford and Kline, eds.,
Explorations in Whitehead’s Philosophy, p. 179.
8
are philosophers who embrace divergence, discord, and change.26 The remainder of the essay
will explore the Whiteheadian/Deleuzian definition of the event against definitions of the city,
particularly the contemporary city.
* * *
As we begin to consider the potential relationships between the expanded theory of the event
provided above, with the contemporary city it is also useful to attempt to define the
contemporary city in general terms. Cites emerged with the development of agriculture and the
production of surplus food, which in turn led to settlements that supported both specialists
(rulers, priests, soldiers, craftsmen, merchants/traders, etc.) and general labour, those not
engaged in agriculture. Essential to the structure of cities were the development of writing to
keep records, a social structure, and technologies (particularly in transportation, tool making, and
weaponry). Therefore, cities have been considered to be both material and immaterial, or social
and formal, and they have been dependent on interconnectivity with the surrounding agricultural
system, and extensive trading networks. Cities draw people together into dense settlements.
Since the emergence of the city in the Neolithic era, the fundamental aspects of the city have
remained, however, the relative emphasis on the component elements has changed. With the
emergence of postmodernity the city has once again gone through dramatic changes in structure,
social organization, and technology.
26 Deleuze, The Fold, p. 81.
9
The influential American urban historian and theorist Lewis Mumford, in his 1937 essay “What
is a City?,” provides one definition of the city when he writes:
The city is a related collection of primary groups and purposive associations….These varied
groups support themselves through economic organizations…and they are all housed in
permanent structures, within a relatively limited area….The city in its complete sense, then,
is a geographic plexus, an economic organization, an institutional process, a theater of social
action, and an aesthetic symbol of collective unity.27
Mumford also provides a general definition of the city in the introduction to his 1938 book The
Culture of Cities, he writes:
The city…is the point of maximum concentration for the power and culture of a
community….The city is the form and symbol of an integrated social relationship: it is the
seat of the temple, the market, the hall of justice, the academy of learning. Here in the city
the goods of civilization are multiplied and manifolded; here is where human experience is
transformed into viable signs, symbols, patterns of conduct, systems of order. Here is where
the issues of civilization are focused….28
Mumford’s definitions provide a clear indication that the city represents for him a relatively
stable condition, that it is the centre of religion, economy, law and education, and that it has a
transformative impact on its citizenry. For Mumford, a city occupies a distinctive location and
10
has material presence, but is also about social relationships, economic systems, laws, and
symbolic structures; much of this accords with a brief description of the city provided by
Whitehead in his book Adventures of Ideas.29 Conventionally cities are also presented as a
reciprocal relationship with rural or agricultural space. As Mumford states cities “are a product
of the earth,”30 and then recounts how the countryside supplies the city with raw resources. This
was historically supported by the clear separation between city and country defined by the city
walls. And yet, cities have always relied on dense inter-relationships, including trade networks,
and lines of supply and demand. According to Mumford, cities as collectivities, tell a particular
story through their structures, the city is a great work of art.31 Here he asserts the concrete over
the spatial, the built city as an enduring testimony to a culture, or civilization. This could be
construed, in the contemporary context, as a nostalgic position. Mumford goes on to state that
cities arise from social needs and create new means of expression. Cities are places of
innovation, whether in art, commerce, or technology. And while Mumford was a great
proponent of the Garden City, he was generally disturbed by the many developments that
occurred in cities since the industrial revolution; the seemingly chaotic, dispersed, and sprawling
nature of cities in particular. Mumford states that urban structures have been unresponsive to
rapid change during the modern era, for Mumford the historic forces that created great cities
seem to have been defeated.32
27 Lewis Mumford, “What is a City?” in R.T. Gates and F. Stout, eds., The City Reader ( London: Routledge, 1996),
pp. 184-85.
28 Lewis Mumford, The Culture of Cities (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, Inc., 1970), p. 3.
29 Alfred North Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas (New York: The Free Press, 1967), pp. 95-97.
30 Mumford, The Culture of Cities, p. 3.
31 Ibid., p. 5.
32 Ibid., p. 8.
11
Against the definitions provided by Mumford, the Italian sociologist Franco Ferrarotti proposes
that the contemporary city can be understood, not just a material structure, but also as a
“collection of messages, a world of meanings, a grid of communications,”33 in other words, as a
multiplicity of systems:
…(a) an economico-ecological or productive system in the first instance; (b) a political
system; (c) a cultural system; (d) a family system, reproductive and relatively educational;
(e) a symbolic system, determined by religious faiths, sacred and profane, revealed or
immanent.34
Ferrarotti notes that Marxian class structures have crumbled, that capital and economic structures
are now very fluid, and that the traditional distinction between country and city is gone. In effect
much of what has been associated with the city may have evaporated in the rapid changes that
cities have been subjected to, he suggests we may be entering a “post-urban” period.35 The city,
country, and wilderness have effectively become part of one large global system; in other words,
the material or formal order of the contemporary city no longer functions as the stable aspect of
urbanism, in the way that it has done historically, cities are more fluid as structures. Ferrarotti’s
definition has some resonance with the definition of the town provided by Deleuze and Guattari:
The town exists only as a function of circulation, and of circuits….It imposes a frequency. It
imposes a polarization of matter, inert, living or human; it causes the phylum, the flow, to
33 Franco Ferrarotti, “ Civil Society as Polyarchic Form: The City,” in P. Kasinitz, ed., Metropolis: Center and
Symbol of Our Times (New York: New York University Press, 1995), p. 452.
34 Ibid., p. 454.
35 Ibid., p. 454.
12
pass through specific places, along horizontal lines. It is a phenomenon of transconsistency,
a network, because it is fundamentally in contact with other towns.36
The Whiteheadian/Deleuzian theory of the event helps to understand the elusive complexity of
the contemporary city. Rather than as a dualistic divide between hard and soft, or material and
social, contemporary cities revolve around a complex interplay of events in time and space. The
economic and cultural roles of cities are changing rapidly, and institutions historically associated
with cities have become much more dispersed. Since the 1940s cites globally have witnessed
rapid and radical change. Even older historic cities have seen significant change in the way they
interact with global forces. Given the Whiteheadian/Deleuzian notion that everything is event,
we then arrive at an understanding of the city as an intensity of particular events in a complex
context that is spatial and temporal and continuously changing. This is a more accurate
depiction of the contemporary city, where it is difficult to pinpoint permanence, although
Whitehead does note that “duration” is an important aspect of societies. Even longstanding
institutions, represented by monumental buildings, are subject to change, as Michel Foucault has
poignantly demonstrated in his writings. Philosophies, based on becoming, tend to be accused of
having nihilistic tendencies, as there is no stable condition onto which meaning can be attached.
However, as Whitehead and Deleuze have demonstrated, the inter-connectedness of everything
suggests that the structure, or ever-changing patterns of events, does provide an affirmation of
cosmic processes. The contemporary city is a dispersed structure, with a completely
interconnected relationship between it and its surroundings, local, regional, and global. Cities
36 Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia (Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press, 1987), p. 432.
13
are complex event structures that can be interpreted as being based on intensities, rather than as
narratives, these intensities can be charted and/or composed.
* * *
Elizabeth Grosz, in her book on post-structuralism and architecture, describes Deleuze as “the
great nomadologist, the thinker of movement, of difference, the cartographer of force rather than
form….”37 The cartography of forces is where the Whiteheadian/Deleuzian theory of event can
provide a preliminary basis for examining the event and the contemporary city. As Grosz also
underscores in her book, Deleuze’s concepts are not meant to be directly applicable in the
manner that many architects have attempted to translate them. However, the theory of the event,
following Whitehead, that Deleuze embraces, with its relationship to contemporary theories of
complexity and chaos, does provide important insights into the world, and the relationships
between sensations, time, space, and structures. The expanded definition of the event provided
above, can encompass the more conventional definition of the event as a distinctive happening,
one that can contribute to a narrative. The narrative is a structured sequence (not necessarily
chronological) of events that occur in time and space, and provides an individual event with a
larger structure into which it can be placed. Clearly, Whitehead and Deleuze present a more
complex concept of the event. The broader definition they embrace could include narrative
structures, but also embraces the entire range of phenomena in space and time, and the impact
events have on prehending bodies, in effect it is a unified theory of the event.
14
A city exists as a complex structure within a larger order of events, a structure that encompasses
and creates events at all levels. The emphasis on the creative, or generative, aspect of events,
informs both Whitehead’s and Deleuze’s work. From the rather difficult definition provided
above, we can begin to develop a number of preliminary concepts that can provide an approach
to the contemporary city. Firstly, the work of Whitehead and Deleuze provides an expanded idea
of what an event is. Events occur in space and time, and affirm the complexity of life as a
constantly changing condition. The emphasis both authors place on the creation of new events is
both affirmative and productive. The definition also gets to the immense complexity of
experience, from the fleeting sensation of a smell to the enduring presence of an architectural
monument. The notion of intensity also plays into this, when the city is understood as a everchanging
network of intensities. As the statement from Deleuze above regarding singularity
attests, the event can also arise out of an unusual coalescing of forces that produce something
like a bottleneck, a point of fusion, or a moment of joy. Here the connection to the operations of
a city becomes more explicit, in that unlike the normative definition of the event that emphasizes
an agent, or actor, and an object or space, the Whiteheadian/Deleuzian formulation implies a
prehending body, however, not necessarily as the active component. There is also a deep
interrelationship between events and objects, what Whitehead terms “ingression,” whether
sensed or physical, and events, and that an object is an event and embodies events is a beneficial
formulation for architects and urbanists. Contemporary cities, as one expect, produce an infinite
range of events on all levels, most of which, like traffic patterns, correspond with the structure of
the city as an immense technical and social construct.
37 Elizabeth Grosz, Architecture from the Outside: Essays on Virtual and Real Space (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
15
Secondly, how events interact is an important aspect of this theory. Given the emphasis on
becoming, and an ever-changing and pluralistic world, made by Whitehead and Deleuze, the
event is a central concept in their work. Events are interrelated, often interpenetrating one
another. The interconnection of events in time and space means that the contemporary city
provides a useful model for describing the complexity of events. In a public park, the greenness
of the space is an event, as are all the environmental aspects, whether wind, sun, seasons, time of
day/night, and/or smells. All of the individual elements that comprise the park are events, these
exist in time so are constantly changing, while retaining an enduring dimension. The use of the
park and its larger context are also events. All of this means that in space and time, a complex
set of forces are continuously creating and shifting the nature of the park. Occasionally a set of
conditions arise that establish a new set of relationships, intensities, or possibilities. Events
establish the park in time and space, affirming its position in a wide range of other forces; it is a
living construct. Here, the biological analogies that resonate in Deleuze’s work in particular, are
also affirmed. Events create a shifting web of inter-connectivity that hold together structures,
and demonstrate the aliveness of a structure; events generate more events. According to
Whitehead, events also create patterns,38 these affirm the aspect of becoming, or that the world is
an organism.
Thirdly, because of their preoccupation with becoming, Whitehead and Deleuze emphasize
process, innovation, and plurality. The ever-changing nature of events, leads to the production
of new events, therefore, there is a creative, or compositional aspect to the structure of events. A
city is comprised of an infinite multitude of events that have occurred and are about to occur;
Press, 2001). p. 60.
16
most are banal, many are new. A sudden convergence of forces, or events, creates a new event, a
sensation, feeling, or structure. Unlike narratology, there is not necessarily a story into which
the event fits. Events, for Whitehead and Deleuze, affirm a greater order, they both use
organisms as the basis for understanding our perceptions of the world. Whitehead, in particular,
against mechanistic and causal models of science developed a “philosophy of organism.”39 This
provides a potential basis for examining cities as analogous to organisms, or ecological
structures.
Returning to the four-part definition of the event outlined above, we can make the following
observations. Firstly, events are a product of time and space, events occur in a temporal and
spatial field; events generate more events. Secondly, events have intensions, or intrinsic
qualities; they belong to all aspects of experience from the most ephemeral to the most enduring.
The emphasis on creativity in both the work of Deleuze and Whitehead, means that events
importantly arise from the convergence of forces that create innovation. The question of
intensify provides intriguing possibilities for those examining structures such as the
contemporary city, as the contemporary city has typically been resistant to conventional methods
of analysis. Thirdly, events are public and move to a private prehending body, the creative
individual is affected. Here the prehending agent, whether human or not, is fully embedded in
events. Fourthly, the important interpenetration of events and objects, the notion of “ingression”
addresses questions of duration and permanence. This is of particular interest to architects and
urbanists who tend to understand a more oppositional relationship between structure and space,
or material and function.
38 See Collingwood, The Idea of Nature, p. 165.
17
The ever-changing patterns of events means that structures can have a harmonic or musical
dimension; this departs from the literary or historic aspect of the more conventional definition.
This unified theory of event overcomes dualism, and encompasses space, time, material,
properties of all events, along with the interrelation between events and those who experience
them. Ultimately, continuously changing patterns of events emerge that affirm the “ontological
realization of the…infinite power of Life….there is no contradiction between the limitless of
becoming and the singularity of the event.”40 As Badiou points out, in his first axiom, Deleuze’s
conception of the event encompasses a general ontology or “infinite power of Life,” for
Whitehead the full complexity of nature. This effort to create an all encompassing theory of
event, means that all that occurs in space, whether in long or short duration, a sensation, or a
structure are events.
The fourth Deleuzian axiom that Badiou identifies, addresses the notion that the event
“composes a life somewhat as a musical composition is organized by a theme.”41 This resonates
with the first axiom, arguing that events have deeper implications beyond the narrative,
structural, or geometrical. The reference to music, implies that events have a musical potential
that resonates with the infinite variety of events occurring at all levels of the world, that there are
structures that link all events together. Whitehead also touches on the notion of rhythm in the
final chapter of his text An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge. A number
of urban theorists, including Henri Lefebvre, also address rhythm, music, and the city. In a
passage that resonates with Whitehead and Deleuze, Mumford writes:
39 See “Whitehead, Alfred North” in A Dictionary of Philosophy (London: Pan Books Ltd., 1979), pp. 345-46.
18
By the diversity of its time-structures, the city in part escapes the tyranny of a single present,
and the monotony of a future that consists in repeating only a single beat heard in the past.
Through its complex orchestration of time and space, no less than through the social division
of labor, life in the city takes on the character of a symphony….42
The notion that contemporary cities are ever-changing harmonic or musical structures composed
by infinite patterns of events seems overwhelming, and yet against current reductivist strategies
employed by design professionals, planners, politicians, and engineers it provides an optimistic
and radically different approach to examining contemporary cities. To conceive of cities as
unified totalities also provides a means for understanding contemporary cities as ecological
entities, structures that resonate with the world.
40 Badiou, “The Event in Deleuze,” p. 38.
41 Ibid., p. 39.
42 Mumford, The Culture of Cities, p. 4.
Hiç yorum yok:
Yorum Gönder